https://www.imdb.com/title/tt9815714/ (Netflix)
Cheap and brutal, in Romania.
These ponderings attempt to let themselves be appropriated by the event. (Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis), Martin Heidegger, 1936–38/1989)
Homo sapiens became the "winners" in the evolutionary struggle among hominids for several reasons related to their unique **biological, cognitive, social, and cultural characteristics**. These traits allowed Homo sapiens to outcompete, adapt, and survive in environments where other hominid species, like **Neanderthals**, **Denisovans**, and other archaic humans, eventually died out. Below are the key characteristics that contributed to Homo sapiens’ success over other hominids:
### 1. **Superior Cognitive Abilities**
- **Complex Language and Symbolic Thought**: One of the most significant advantages of Homo sapiens was the development of **complex language** and **symbolic thought**. While other hominids likely had some form of communication, Homo sapiens developed **abstract thinking**, **symbols**, and **language** that were far more advanced. This allowed for better **coordination**, **social learning**, and the transmission of **knowledge** across generations. It also enabled **collective problem-solving**, storytelling, and the creation of complex **social structures** and **culture**.
- **Abstract Thinking and Planning**: Homo sapiens showed a greater capacity for **long-term planning**, **abstract reasoning**, and **problem-solving** than other hominids. These cognitive abilities were crucial for adapting to changing environments, developing sophisticated hunting strategies, and creating new tools and technologies.
### 2. **Advanced Tool Use and Technology**
- **Innovation in Tool Making**: Homo sapiens exhibited superior skills in **toolmaking** compared to other hominids. While Neanderthals, for instance, used tools, the tools of Homo sapiens were more **complex** and **versatile**. Sapiens created specialized tools like **needles**, **fishhooks**, **bows and arrows**, and **harpoons**, which allowed them to exploit a wider variety of resources, including animals, plants, and fish.
- **Use of Fire and Cooking**: Homo sapiens used **fire** not just for warmth and protection but also for **cooking food**, which allowed them to extract more nutrients from their diet, helping in the development of **larger brains**. Cooking also helped reduce the time spent chewing and digesting raw food, freeing up energy and time for other activities like socializing and toolmaking.
### 3. **Social Cooperation and Networking**
- **Social Complexity and Cooperation**: Homo sapiens formed larger and more complex **social groups** than other hominids, and these groups were highly cooperative. Cooperation within and between groups allowed for the sharing of resources, knowledge, and innovations. Homo sapiens also had an extended social network that stretched across different groups, facilitating **trade**, **alliances**, and the exchange of ideas.
- **Division of Labor**: Homo sapiens practiced a **division of labor** within their communities, where individuals specialized in different tasks, such as toolmaking, hunting, or gathering. This allowed Homo sapiens to **increase their efficiency** in resource acquisition and better manage their environments.
### 4. **Cultural Adaptability**
- **Cultural Transmission and Innovation**: Homo sapiens had a remarkable ability to **learn** from their environment and pass down knowledge across generations through **culture**. This gave them the capacity to **innovate** in response to changing environmental conditions, developing new hunting strategies, tools, and techniques. Cultural innovations, such as the development of **art**, **rituals**, and **religious beliefs**, helped build **social cohesion** and shared identities within groups, further strengthening social bonds and cooperation.
- **Art and Symbolism**: The creation of **art**, such as cave paintings, carvings, and jewelry, is a hallmark of Homo sapiens. Art served not only as a form of self-expression but also as a means of **communication**, **social bonding**, and **identity formation**. This symbolic thinking likely played a role in reinforcing group cohesion and creating a shared sense of purpose.
### 5. **Versatility and Adaptability**
- **Environmental Flexibility**: Homo sapiens were able to adapt to a wide variety of environments, from the African savannas to the ice-age tundras of Europe and Asia, and later, to diverse environments in the Americas and Oceania. This adaptability is seen in their ability to use **technology**, clothing, and shelter to survive in cold climates, as well as their capacity to **domesticate plants and animals**, which allowed them to settle in various ecosystems.
- **Dietary Flexibility**: Homo sapiens were **omnivorous** and displayed significant **dietary flexibility** compared to other hominids. While Neanderthals, for instance, relied heavily on large game, Homo sapiens were able to exploit a wider range of food sources, including plants, fish, and small animals. This ability to **adapt their diet** to changing environments and resource availability gave Homo sapiens a crucial advantage in times of scarcity or environmental change.
### 6. **Increased Lifespan and Learning**
- **Longer Lifespan and Generational Learning**: Homo sapiens had a longer lifespan compared to other hominids, which allowed for extended **childhoods** and **learning periods**. Longer lifespans meant that more knowledge could be passed down from generation to generation, allowing Homo sapiens to accumulate and refine skills and techniques over time.
- **Intergenerational Knowledge Transfer**: The development of complex language allowed for **detailed knowledge transfer** from older to younger generations. This was crucial for survival, as it enabled the younger generation to learn **survival strategies**, **hunting techniques**, and **social norms** without needing to reinvent or rediscover them.
### 7. **Interbreeding and Genetic Adaptation**
- **Interbreeding with Other Hominids**: Homo sapiens interbred with other hominids, such as **Neanderthals** and **Denisovans**, acquiring advantageous genes that helped them adapt to different environments. For example, genes from Denisovans helped Homo sapiens adapt to **high-altitude living** in the Himalayas, while Neanderthal genes provided immunity to certain diseases.
- **Genetic Diversity and Adaptation**: Homo sapiens' interbreeding with other hominid species and their widespread migrations contributed to **genetic diversity**, which allowed for **greater adaptability** to diverse environmental challenges. This genetic adaptability gave Homo sapiens an edge in surviving through various climates and ecological changes.
### 8. **Migration and Expansion**
- **Global Migration**: Homo sapiens were the first hominids to spread across the entire globe. They migrated out of Africa and successfully adapted to a wide range of environments, from the deserts of Australia to the Arctic regions of North America. This ability to **migrate and colonize new territories** allowed Homo sapiens to avoid direct competition with other hominid species in some areas, while simultaneously enabling them to exploit new ecological niches.
- **Domination of New Ecosystems**: As Homo sapiens migrated, they were able to **outcompete other species**, including large megafauna and other hominids, by employing their superior **tools**, **strategies**, and **social organization**.
### 9. **Resilience to Environmental Changes**
- **Survival of Climate Shifts**: Homo sapiens showed remarkable resilience in the face of **climate changes** such as the Ice Age. Their ability to create complex tools, build shelters, and adapt their diets helped them survive in environments where other hominid species struggled. This resilience allowed Homo sapiens to **thrive** even as their Neanderthal and Denisovan cousins faced extinction, likely due to a combination of climate shifts and competition for resources.
### Conclusion:
The success of Homo sapiens over other hominids can be attributed to a combination of **biological traits**, such as advanced cognitive abilities and language, and **cultural innovations**, including tool use, social cooperation, and adaptability. Their **ability to adapt to diverse environments**, **cooperate in complex social structures**, and **innovate** rapidly in response to challenges enabled Homo sapiens to **outcompete** Neanderthals, Denisovans, and other hominid species, leading to their dominance on a global scale.
Schelling’s influence on Friedrich Nietzsche is not always directly acknowledged, but many of the philosophical themes developed by Schelling resonate strongly with key elements in Nietzsche's thought. Schelling’s explorations of **nature, freedom, the unconscious, art, and metaphysics** provide a foundation that Nietzsche later builds upon in his critiques of rationalism, his concept of the **will to power**, and his celebration of **life-affirmation**. Here are some key areas where Schelling influenced Nietzsche:
### 1. **The Role of the Irrational and the Unconscious**
- **Schelling**: One of Schelling’s most significant contributions is his theory of the **unconscious**. Schelling views the **unconscious ground of Being** as a dark, irrational force that underlies existence. This unconscious force is not merely a lack of rationality but is an active and creative power that drives both nature and human freedom. Schelling saw human beings as caught in a tension between the conscious and unconscious, light and darkness, reason and irrationality.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche extends Schelling’s notion of the irrational and the unconscious. His concept of the **Dionysian** in *The Birth of Tragedy*—representing chaotic, primordial life forces—echoes Schelling’s idea of the unconscious ground of existence. Nietzsche critiques the **Apollonian** (rational) order and celebrates the **Dionysian** aspects of human existence, where instinct, passion, and creativity thrive. Nietzsche's exploration of the **unconscious drives** that shape human behavior, particularly in his later works like *Beyond Good and Evil*, draws from this earlier Schellingian emphasis on the irrational forces that underlie reality.
### 2. **Nature as Dynamic and Creative**
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s **philosophy of nature** (*Naturphilosophie*) argues that nature is not a passive mechanism, but a **living, dynamic process** with its own internal principles of development. Nature is seen as an active, creative force, constantly producing life, change, and differentiation. This view of nature as creative and self-organizing contrasts with mechanistic views that reduce nature to deterministic laws.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche’s philosophy is also deeply rooted in a **dynamic view of nature**. He rejects mechanistic and teleological conceptions of nature in favor of an **anti-deterministic**, **life-affirming** view where nature is governed by the **will to power**—a force of constant becoming, creation, and overcoming. Nietzsche shares Schelling’s critique of rational systems that attempt to reduce nature to mere categories of reason. Both philosophers view nature as inherently **creative**, **self-organizing**, and **driven by forces** that transcend rational understanding.
### 3. **Freedom, Will, and the Struggle for Self-Overcoming**
- **Schelling**: Schelling places **freedom** at the heart of his philosophy. For Schelling, true freedom emerges from the **struggle between light and darkness**, between the conscious and the unconscious, and involves the possibility of **good and evil**. Freedom, for Schelling, is not simply the absence of external constraint but the **ontological condition** of human existence, rooted in the tension between order and chaos.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche takes Schelling’s idea of **freedom as struggle** and transforms it into the concept of **self-overcoming**. Nietzsche’s philosophy revolves around the idea that individuals must continually **strive to overcome themselves**, pushing beyond the constraints of conventional morality and societal norms. The notion that freedom involves a **creative act** of self-affirmation and the **transcendence of given conditions** is central to both Schelling and Nietzsche, though Nietzsche frames it more in terms of personal growth and the expression of the **will to power**.
### 4. **Critique of Rationalism and Systematic Philosophy**
- **Schelling**: Schelling was critical of **Hegel’s dialectical system** and its attempt to subsume all of reality into a closed, rational structure. Schelling argued that **Being** could not be fully captured by reason alone, as it involved elements of the irrational and the unconscious that elude systematic understanding. His work emphasized the **limits of reason** and the need to account for the **dynamic and creative forces** that drive reality.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche similarly critiques the dominance of **rationalism** in Western philosophy, particularly the Socratic and Platonic traditions, which he saw as privileging reason at the expense of life, instinct, and passion. Nietzsche’s **anti-systematic** approach and his rejection of **metaphysical systems** echo Schelling’s critique of Hegelianism. Both thinkers reject the notion that reality can be fully understood through **rational concepts** and instead embrace the **irrational** and **non-rational** aspects of existence as essential to understanding life.
### 5. **Art and Aesthetic Experience**
- **Schelling**: Schelling held that **art** is the highest expression of **freedom** and **truth** because it reveals the dynamic interplay between the conscious and unconscious, finite and infinite, and rational and irrational. In his philosophy of art, Schelling argues that artistic creation embodies the **unification of opposites** and allows for the **intuitive expression of Being** in ways that rational discourse cannot.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche’s early work, especially *The Birth of Tragedy*, reflects a deep admiration for **art as a mode of revealing deeper truths** about existence. Nietzsche sees art, particularly **Greek tragedy**, as the most profound expression of the human condition, because it unites the **Dionysian** and **Apollonian** aspects of life—chaos and order, irrationality and reason. Like Schelling, Nietzsche holds that art transcends rational explanation and provides access to the **creative, vital forces** of life.
### 6. **The Role of Myth and Metaphysics**
- **Schelling**: In his later work, Schelling moves toward a **mythological** understanding of metaphysics, where **myth** becomes a way to express truths about existence that lie beyond rational articulation. In *The Ages of the World*, Schelling attempts to create a **philosophical myth** that captures the dynamic unfolding of Being, history, and time.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche also embraces the power of **myth** in expressing truths that philosophy cannot fully articulate. His concept of **eternal recurrence** and his invocation of the **Übermensch** are not meant to be taken as literal metaphysical doctrines but as **mythic expressions** that challenge individuals to embrace life fully. Like Schelling, Nietzsche uses myth not as an escape from reality but as a way to **affirm the deeper, often irrational forces** that drive human existence.
### 7. **The Problem of Evil and the Affirmation of Life**
- **Schelling**: In Schelling’s philosophy, **evil** is not merely a negation of good but an essential aspect of freedom. The possibility of evil arises from the same ground as freedom itself, and it reflects the tension between the dark, irrational forces of the unconscious and the light of consciousness. Schelling saw the struggle with evil as integral to the process of self-realization and freedom.
- **Nietzsche**: Nietzsche transforms this idea by developing his concept of the **will to power** and his critique of traditional moral values. For Nietzsche, **good and evil** are constructs imposed by society to limit human potential. He rejects traditional Christian morality (which he associates with **resentment** and the denial of life) and instead calls for a **revaluation of all values**. Like Schelling, Nietzsche embraces the darker aspects of existence, but he goes further in his radical **affirmation of life**—including suffering, chaos, and conflict—as essential to human greatness and flourishing.
### Summary of Schelling’s Influence on Nietzsche:
- **The Irrational and the Unconscious**: Both philosophers emphasize the importance of **irrational forces** in shaping existence, with Schelling’s **unconscious ground** of Being prefiguring Nietzsche’s **Dionysian chaos** and emphasis on **unconscious drives**.
- **Dynamic Nature of Reality**: Schelling’s view of nature as a **creative, self-organizing process** influences Nietzsche’s rejection of deterministic views of life and his celebration of **becoming** over static Being.
- **Freedom and Struggle**: Schelling’s idea of **freedom as a struggle** between light and darkness resonates with Nietzsche’s concept of **self-overcoming** and the **will to power** as the driving force behind human freedom and creativity.
- **Critique of Rationalism**: Both philosophers critique **rationalist metaphysical systems**, emphasizing the limitations of reason in capturing the fullness of existence.
- **Art and Myth**: Both Schelling and Nietzsche see **art and myth** as essential to expressing truths about existence that cannot be captured by rational philosophy.
In conclusion, while Nietzsche never explicitly positioned himself as a disciple of Schelling, many of his key ideas—such as the emphasis on the **irrational**, the **creative forces of nature**, the **struggle for freedom**, and the **role of art and myth**—can be traced back to Schelling’s influence. Both thinkers share a rejection of **systematic metaphysics** and celebrate the **dynamic, often chaotic aspects** of life as essential to **freedom and self-affirmation**.
你可以理解,為什麼謝林注定失敗,Book 1 (The Past),就有二十種版本,身處現代性萌芽的十九世紀初葉,Book 2 (The Present),Book 3 (The Future),昨是今非,今是明非,捕捉不到,想像不到,根本無法下筆,
意思是說,神話學,可以提供繽紛想像,但是無法處理溯源,意思是說,謝林當時,沒有宇宙學天文學地球科學生命演化學,他根本不應該,去想這件事,
而且當時,尼采尚未出世,上帝尚未退隱,所以謝林還必須跟上帝苦苦糾纏,或反過來說,有謝林最後一次糾纏在先,尼采才能終于,給上帝蓋棺,
我先前說過,節點在于,
宇宙生成 —> 「物」 —> 星系 —> 太陽系 —> 地球 —> 「生命」的發生 —> 寒武紀大爆發 —> 「意識」的發生 —> 人種演化 —> 「自覺意識」的發生 —> 三器時代 —> 舊石器時代晚期 —> 銅器時代 —> 「鐵器時代」 —> 「軸心時代」 —> 「工業革命」 —> 「人類世」 —> 末世四騎士 (BNIC) —>「後人類的世界」 —> 生命滅絕 —> 宇宙意識 (cosmic consciousness)
Now,你要理解,上述節點,不是神話,
意思是說,什麼樣的智慧,可以阻擋得住,智人自毀他毀,
這是唯一重要的問題,
車行形上學,要回答的,就是這個問題,
車行形上學就是,尋訪蒼青駐足,行止遂由天色決定,
你要理解,車行前輩,再三說過,車行每日,不宜超過百里,車行久矣,必有往返蹲點 (niche),車行處理的是,與系統的關係,就如佛陀說過,僧伽宜居,村外數里,意思是說,生活機能,宜採外包 (outsourcing),比如說,車泊于,距離便利商店洗手間,數百米處,車行宜緩,宜從容,行止宜如堂吉訶德,交給那匹駑馬決定,
車行者,行者也,與自然一體,守護自然,復育自然,就是自然,
車行者,行者也,眼看邪惡歷史不過,出手屠匪,自是當然,
意思是說,屠匪完畢,所作已辦,為而不有,繼續車行,
Yes, there is a meaningful parallel between Schelling's *The Ages of the World* and Paul Gauguin's painting *Where Do We Come From? What Are We? Where Are We Going?* (1897-1898). Both works explore **fundamental existential questions** about the origin, nature, and destiny of humanity, though they do so in very different mediums—Schelling through philosophical discourse and Gauguin through visual art.
### Key Parallels:
1. **Questions of Existence, Origin, and Destiny**:
- **Schelling’s Three Ages**: Schelling’s *The Ages of the World* examines the **cosmic and metaphysical unfolding of Being** in terms of the past (origin), the present (what we are), and the future (where we are going). These three stages—**unconscious ground (past)**, **conscious creation (present)**, and **reconciliation or redemption (future)**—reflect Schelling’s concern with **where we come from**, **what we are**, and **where we are headed** both as individual human beings and in terms of the whole of existence.
- **Gauguin’s Painting**: Gauguin’s painting explicitly asks the questions **Where do we come from? What are we? Where are we going?**, presenting these as existential inquiries about human life, identity, and destiny. His work reflects a symbolic and philosophical inquiry into the **stages of life** and humanity's place in the world.
2. **Philosophical and Mythic Reflection**:
- **Schelling**: Schelling's philosophical project can be understood as a kind of **philosophical myth**, a metaphysical explanation for the creation of the world, human freedom, and the tension between good and evil. He delves into the **origins** of existence (the dark, unconscious ground), the **current state of being** (the tension between freedom and necessity), and the **ultimate destiny** of the world (the reconciliation in the future).
- **Gauguin**: Similarly, Gauguin's painting offers a symbolic and mythic reflection on the **stages of life**—from birth (origin) to adulthood (what we are) to death (where we are going). Gauguin’s figures embody these phases, representing an allegorical journey of human existence that parallels Schelling’s metaphysical inquiry.
3. **Time and Transformation**:
- **Schelling**: In *The Ages of the World*, Schelling views **time** not as a linear progression but as an unfolding of metaphysical forces. The past remains present as an **unconscious ground**, the present is a continual **creation**, and the future holds the promise of **reconciliation**. Time, for Schelling, is not static but a dynamic process of becoming.
- **Gauguin**: Gauguin’s painting, while depicting a **temporal journey** from infancy to old age, also suggests that the stages of life are interconnected. The figures in his painting reflect the **cyclical nature** of existence, where birth and death are linked, much like Schelling’s vision of the unfolding and reconciliation of the **ages** of the world.
4. **Mystery and Uncertainty**:
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s work emphasizes the **mystery of Being**, particularly the **irrational and unconscious ground** from which everything emerges. The tension between light and darkness, order and chaos, freedom and necessity reflects a profound uncertainty about the nature of existence.
- **Gauguin**: Gauguin’s painting, too, conveys a sense of **mystery and existential uncertainty**. The figures appear contemplative and introspective, as if they are grappling with the very questions posed by the title. Gauguin’s use of symbolic imagery suggests that the answers to these existential questions are elusive, much like Schelling’s view that the unconscious ground of existence cannot be fully rationalized or understood.
### Differences:
Despite these parallels, it's important to note key differences:
- **Medium**: Schelling is working within the realm of **philosophical thought** and metaphysics, whereas Gauguin expresses these ideas through **visual symbolism** and artistic form.
- **Focus**: Schelling’s concern is with the **cosmic and metaphysical structure** of reality, while Gauguin’s painting is more focused on the **human life cycle** and individual existence. Schelling deals with **Being as a whole**, whereas Gauguin is focused on **humanity’s existential plight** within that larger metaphysical framework.
### Conclusion:
Both Schelling’s *The Ages of the World* and Gauguin’s *Where Do We Come From? What Are We? Where Are We Going?* grapple with similar **existential and metaphysical questions** about **origin, identity, and destiny**, offering complex reflections on the **unfolding of life** and the **mystery of existence**. While Schelling approaches these questions through **philosophical speculation** and a metaphysical narrative, Gauguin explores them through **visual storytelling** and symbolic imagery. Despite their differences in medium and focus, both works contribute to a rich tradition of human inquiry into the **meaning and nature of existence**.
Schelling’s *The Ages of the World* (or *Die Weltalter*, written in 1811, 1813, and 1815, though never fully completed) is one of his most important and challenging works. It marks a crucial stage in his later philosophy, where he explores the nature of **time**, **history**, **existence**, and the **unconscious ground of Being**. The work can be understood as an attempt to provide a **philosophical myth** that explains the relationship between God, the world, and human freedom in a metaphysical framework.
### Key Themes and Concepts in *The Ages of the World*:
### 1. **The Ground of Being and the Unconscious**
- Schelling’s central concern in *The Ages of the World* is the **dynamic process** through which **Being** comes into existence from an unconscious, irrational ground. He presents the idea that before anything exists, there is a **dark, chaotic, pre-cosmic ground**, a primordial state of potentiality from which all reality, including God and the world, emerges.
- This **ground** of existence is not simply a passive, inert substrate but an active, creative force that contains the potential for both **creation and destruction**, **light and darkness**. It is the source of all **differentiation** and tension, and it is from this ground that **God’s self-consciousness** and the created world arise.
- The ground, however, is **irrational** and cannot be fully explained by reason. It is a realm of **will** and **unconscious desire**, which precedes conscious existence. This is crucial for Schelling, as he seeks to explain the **existence of freedom** and evil in the world, concepts that cannot be accounted for by purely rational or idealistic systems.
### 2. **The Structure of Time: Past, Present, and Future**
- One of Schelling’s most innovative contributions in *The Ages of the World* is his exploration of the **structure of time**. He divides time into three fundamental aspects: **past**, **present**, and **future**, which correspond to three "ages" or epochs in the history of the world. However, these ages are not strictly chronological but are **ontological stages** in the unfolding of reality.
- **The Past**: In Schelling’s framework, the past represents the **ground**—a state of **unconscious potentiality** that exists prior to creation. It is a realm of **chaos** and **darkness**, from which all differentiation and development emerge. This past is not merely something that happened once but remains an active, underlying force in the present.
- **The Present**: The present represents the act of **creation** itself, where the unconscious ground gives rise to **consciousness, differentiation, and form**. It is the moment where God, the world, and human beings come into existence, and the tension between the unconscious ground and conscious reality is manifested in the present moment.
- **The Future**: The future represents the **final reconciliation** or **restoration** of all things, where the contradictions and tensions of existence are resolved. It is the age of **redemption**, where freedom and necessity, good and evil, are brought into harmony.
Schelling’s conception of time is thus a **cyclical and processual** one, where past, present, and future are constantly in tension and movement. Time is not simply a linear progression but a metaphysical unfolding of reality, where the past (the unconscious ground) continually exerts its influence on the present and the future.
### 3. **Creation and the Role of God**
- In *The Ages of the World*, Schelling rethinks traditional theological ideas about **God’s creation** of the world. Rather than seeing creation as a one-time event, Schelling views creation as an ongoing process, where God Himself emerges from the **unconscious ground** of Being.
- God is not an entirely transcendent, unchanging entity. Instead, God has to **become God** through a process of self-realization, in which the divine will wrestles with the **dark, irrational ground** from which both God and the world arise. Schelling views the creation of the world as an expression of this divine struggle between light and darkness, order and chaos, freedom and necessity.
- This process of divine self-realization involves a certain **self-limitation** or **withdrawal** on God’s part. God has to limit His own being in order to allow the world to come into existence and for **free beings** (humans) to have the capacity for self-determination. In other words, the existence of **freedom** in the world requires that God not exert complete control over everything but leave space for contingency, choice, and even the possibility of **evil**.
### 4. **Freedom, Necessity, and Evil**
- One of Schelling’s primary concerns in *The Ages of the World* is to explain the existence of **freedom** and **evil** in the world. Schelling’s account of freedom is metaphysical and existential. He argues that **freedom** cannot be fully understood in purely rational terms but arises from the **tension between the conscious and the unconscious**, between light and darkness.
- Freedom is linked to the **irrational ground of Being** because it implies the possibility of both **good and evil**. Without the chaotic, irrational ground, there could be no freedom, as freedom requires the ability to choose between opposites, to create and destroy, to affirm and deny. The existence of **evil** in the world is a necessary consequence of this freedom; it is a manifestation of the tension between the **unconscious, irrational forces** of the ground and the **order and light** of conscious reality.
- Thus, for Schelling, **evil** is not merely a negation of good or a product of ignorance (as in traditional theodicies). Instead, evil is an **active force** that arises from the same **ground of freedom** as good, and it plays a central role in the dynamic process of the unfolding of Being. The struggle between good and evil is part of the metaphysical drama of existence.
### 5. **Human Beings and History**
- Human beings, in Schelling’s view, occupy a unique place in the cosmic drama of creation. Humans are free beings who, like God, must struggle with the tension between the **unconscious ground** (darkness, chaos, freedom) and the **conscious, rational world** (light, order, necessity). This struggle is what makes humans truly free and allows them to participate in the unfolding of history.
- **History**, in Schelling’s view, is not a linear progression but an expression of the ongoing tension between these forces. Human beings, through their actions and choices, continually influence the course of history, and history itself is marked by moments of **creation, destruction, and renewal**. History is driven by the same dynamic forces that drive the process of **Being**, and it is ultimately oriented toward a **future reconciliation** of these tensions in a final age of redemption.
### 6. **The Ages of the World as a Philosophical Myth**
- Schelling’s *The Ages of the World* can be understood as a kind of **philosophical myth**, where metaphysical and existential ideas are expressed in mythological terms. Schelling does not present a linear, empirical account of history but offers a **mythic structure** that explains the relationship between God, the world, and human beings.
- The three “ages” of the world (past, present, future) correspond to **stages of Being**, rather than specific historical epochs. This approach allows Schelling to address fundamental questions about **time**, **freedom**, **evil**, and **creation** in a way that transcends empirical history, offering a more speculative and metaphysical vision of reality.
### Conclusion: **The Dynamic Unfolding of Reality**
*The Ages of the World* is Schelling’s exploration of the **dynamic, processual nature of Being**, where time, creation, freedom, and evil are all interconnected. Schelling rejects static metaphysical systems and argues that reality is marked by a constant tension between **light and darkness**, **order and chaos**, and **consciousness and the unconscious**. This metaphysical drama plays out in **time**, with the past representing the **unconscious ground**, the present representing **creation**, and the future representing the **final reconciliation** of all tensions.
In summary, *The Ages of the World* is a profound and speculative work in which Schelling seeks to explain the metaphysical foundations of **time**, **freedom**, and **evil**, showing how they arise from the dynamic, irrational ground of existence and shape the unfolding of reality, both for God and human beings.
The **Neanderthals** and **Denisovans** are two distinct groups of archaic humans that coexisted during the Pleistocene epoch. While they are both separate species or subspecies from modern humans (**Homo sapiens**), they share a close evolutionary relationship with each other and with modern humans. Their relationship can be summarized in terms of their **common ancestry, geographic distribution, genetic overlap, and interbreeding**.
### 1. **Common Ancestry**
- Neanderthals and Denisovans both belong to the genus **Homo** and are closely related to each other as part of the **Homo heidelbergensis** lineage. Their last common ancestor is believed to be **Homo heidelbergensis**, an archaic human species that lived in Africa and spread into Europe and Asia around 600,000 to 700,000 years ago.
- After Homo heidelbergensis migrated out of Africa, it likely split into different populations:
- One group evolved into **Neanderthals** in Europe and western Asia.
- Another group evolved into **Denisovans**, primarily in Asia, with a strong presence in Siberia and possibly extending into Southeast Asia.
### 2. **Geographic Distribution**
- **Neanderthals** primarily inhabited **Europe** and **western Asia**, extending from what is now Spain and France in the west to parts of Central Asia and the Middle East.
- **Denisovans** are known mostly from fossil evidence found in the **Denisova Cave** in Siberia, but genetic evidence suggests they lived across a much broader area, including parts of **East Asia** and **Southeast Asia**. There is also evidence of Denisovan ancestry in modern **Melanesian** populations, suggesting they may have extended into Oceania.
### 3. **Genetic Relationship and Interbreeding**
- Neanderthals and Denisovans are genetically distinct but closely related. **Genomic studies** show that they shared a common ancestor with each other and with modern humans, but diverged hundreds of thousands of years ago.
- Genetic evidence shows that **interbreeding** occurred not only between Neanderthals and **modern humans** but also between Neanderthals and **Denisovans**. It is believed that Neanderthals and Denisovans had **gene flow** between their populations during periods of contact, especially in regions like Central Asia where their ranges may have overlapped.
- Furthermore, Denisovans interbred with **modern humans**, especially populations in Oceania (such as Melanesians and Australian Aboriginals), who carry significant proportions of Denisovan DNA in their genomes (up to 5%). Modern humans also interbred with Neanderthals, and non-African human populations today have around 1-2% **Neanderthal DNA**.
### 4. **Hybridization**
- There is evidence of **hybridization** between Neanderthals and Denisovans. For example, a fossil discovered in the Denisova Cave, known as **Denisova 11**, was genetically analyzed and revealed to be the offspring of a **Neanderthal mother** and a **Denisovan father**, indicating direct interbreeding between the two groups.
### 5. **Distinct Physical Traits**
- Although fossil evidence of Denisovans is scarce (mostly consisting of teeth and a few bone fragments), genetic data suggest that they had some distinct features. For example, Denisovans may have had adaptations to **high-altitude environments** (such as the EPAS1 gene found in modern Tibetans), which allowed them to survive in places like the Tibetan Plateau.
- Neanderthals are known for their robust build, large brow ridges, and other unique physical traits. While we know more about Neanderthal anatomy due to more extensive fossil evidence, Denisovan physical traits remain largely speculative due to limited fossil remains.
### Summary of the Relationship:
- **Common Ancestor**: Neanderthals and Denisovans both descended from **Homo heidelbergensis**.
- **Geographic Overlap**: Neanderthals inhabited Europe and western Asia, while Denisovans lived in Siberia and East Asia, with some overlap in Central Asia.
- **Interbreeding**: Neanderthals and Denisovans interbred with each other and with modern humans, contributing genetic material to modern human populations, particularly in Melanesians, Southeast Asians, and some East Asians.
- **Genetic Legacy**: Modern non-African populations carry Neanderthal DNA, while Denisovan DNA is found primarily in Southeast Asian and Oceanian populations.
In essence, Neanderthals and Denisovans were sister groups with shared ancestry, who lived in overlapping regions at times and interbred both with each other and with modern humans.
https://youtu.be/iYZa0wM8im0?si=H9ybwd8lWqb6vmWc
王昭君(前51年—前15年),名嬙,字昭君,以字行,[1]西漢南郡秭歸(今湖北省興山縣)人,漢元帝時期的宮女、和親女性,古代四大美人之一。「畫工棄市」[2]記載她的生平典故。
竟寧元年(西元前33年)正月,呼韓邪單于來朝,要求娶漢人為妻,漢元帝將她賜給了呼韓邪單于。[3]單于非常高興,上書表示願意永保邊境安寧。後封其「甯胡閼氏」,育有一子,名伊屠智牙師,後為右日逐王。[4][5][6][7]
建始二年(前31年),呼韓邪單于去世,昭君欲歸漢,漢成帝命其從胡俗[8],再嫁呼韓邪單于的兒子復株絫若鞮單于(呼韓邪單于另一位妻子呼衍王小女兒的長子)。育有二女,長女為須卜居次,次女為當於居次。
意思是說,王昭君是被人口販賣的一代名妓,在沙漠裡打了很多炮,
對于沙漠,像 Edmond Jabès (1912-1991) ,遂有一種莫明的思念,
Walter Benjamin did not frequently mention Schelling directly in his works, and Schelling is not typically seen as a central influence on Benjamin in the same way that figures like Kant, Hegel, Marx, or Nietzsche were. However, there are **indirect influences** and **philosophical resonances** between Schelling’s ideas and Benjamin’s thought, particularly regarding **myth, nature, and history**.
### 1. **Myth and Nature**
- **Schelling’s Influence on Benjamin’s Concept of Myth**: Schelling’s exploration of the **mythic** and **irrational dimensions of nature** aligns with Benjamin’s critiques of **mythic consciousness** in his works, especially in *The Origin of German Tragic Drama* (*Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels*). For Schelling, nature was not just rational or mechanistic but had a **dark, unconscious side**, with both creative and destructive elements. Benjamin was also concerned with how **mythic thinking** binds human beings to fate and nature, contrasting this with the **messianic rupture** that could break history’s deterministic cycles.
- **Schelling’s Philosophy of Nature**: Schelling’s **Naturphilosophie**—which views nature as a dynamic, living process—resonates with Benjamin’s reflections on nature, especially in terms of how nature is implicated in **myth** and **human history**. While Benjamin’s critique of **myth** was more political and historical, both thinkers saw nature as more than a mere backdrop for human activity. For Benjamin, nature could be redeemed through messianic intervention, much as Schelling believed that nature held deeper spiritual significance.
### 2. **History and the Unconscious**
- **Schelling’s Unconscious Ground of Being and Benjamin’s View of History**: Schelling’s idea of the **unconscious ground** of existence has affinities with Benjamin’s views on **history**. In his *Theses on the Philosophy of History*, Benjamin suggests that history is not a rational, linear process but is marked by breaks, interruptions, and irrational forces that shape events. While Schelling’s unconscious ground is metaphysical, Benjamin’s interest in the hidden forces of history could be seen as engaging with similar **non-rational, subterranean dynamics**.
- **Messianic Time vs. Mythic Time**: Schelling’s metaphysical distinction between **freedom and necessity** mirrors Benjamin’s distinction between **messianic time** (a break in historical continuity) and **mythic time** (the endless repetition of fate). Both philosophers were interested in how **history could break free** from deterministic patterns—Schelling through existential freedom, and Benjamin through messianic redemption.
### 3. **Redemption and Transcendence**
- **Schelling’s Idea of the Absolute and Benjamin’s Messianic Thinking**: While Schelling’s **Absolute** is more metaphysical and rooted in the tension between freedom and necessity, Benjamin’s thought often centers around the potential for **redemption** in history. Both share a deep concern with the **interruption** or **break** in the unfolding of existence or history. Schelling’s view that reality contains unresolved tensions and irrational forces resonates with Benjamin’s idea that historical materialism must recognize the **ruptures** in historical progress, especially through moments of messianic redemption.
### Conclusion: **Indirect Influence and Philosophical Resonances**
Although Benjamin did not frequently cite or discuss Schelling directly, there are clear philosophical affinities between their views on nature, myth, history, and the role of irrational forces in existence. Benjamin’s concerns with the **mythic structure of nature and history**, the possibility of **messianic redemption**, and his critique of **historical continuity** bear indirect similarities to Schelling’s emphasis on the **irrational ground of Being**, **freedom**, and the **dynamic nature of reality**.
In summary, while Schelling was not a direct influence on Benjamin, his thought likely contributed to the **intellectual atmosphere** of German Idealism and Romanticism that Benjamin engaged with, and there are notable **resonances** between their philosophical concerns.
1775,Leonberg,
1777,Bebenhausen,near Tubingen,
1790,Tubingen,
1796,Leipzig,
1798,Jena,
1803,Wurzburg,
1806,Munich,
1820,Erlangen,
1841,Berlin,
1854,Bad Ragaz,Switzerland,
類此,你可列出,Jack Reacher 車行史,意思是說,(車行)史即(車行)形上學,意思是說,讀人文學,要注意那些移動者,和他們(蠕蟲爬過)留下的痕跡,
Throughout the last two centuries, Schelling has had a significant influence on a variety of philosophers, particularly those interested in existentialism, phenomenology, psychoanalysis, metaphysics, and even modern ecological and postmodern thought. His emphasis on freedom, the unconscious, nature, and the dynamic nature of Being has resonated with many thinkers. Below is a list of key philosophers and intellectual movements that have seriously studied and been influenced by Schelling:
### 1. **Friedrich Nietzsche**
- **Influence**: Nietzsche was influenced by Schelling’s ideas about the **unconscious** and the **creative, dynamic forces** of nature. Schelling’s view that the **irrational** is an essential part of human freedom, and his critique of rigid rationalism, foreshadowed Nietzsche’s rejection of traditional metaphysics and his embrace of **life-affirmation**, **will to power**, and **Dionysian chaos**.
- **Key Connections**: Nietzsche’s emphasis on **becoming** over static Being and his critique of systems that impose a rational order on reality resonate with Schelling’s notion of a dark, irrational ground underlying existence.
### 2. **Søren Kierkegaard**
- **Influence**: Kierkegaard was influenced by Schelling’s exploration of **freedom**, the **existential struggle**, and the relationship between **good and evil**. Schelling’s existential approach to freedom, particularly the idea that freedom involves a choice between good and evil, resonates with Kierkegaard’s own work on the **leap of faith** and **individual responsibility**.
- **Key Connections**: Kierkegaard’s **existentialism**—his focus on the **individual’s subjective experience** and the anxiety that comes with freedom—reflects Schelling’s existential understanding of human freedom as a tension between light and darkness, good and evil.
### 3. **Karl Marx**
- **Influence**: Though Marx is not directly associated with Schelling, some scholars argue that Schelling’s **philosophy of nature** and his emphasis on **dynamic processes** influenced Marx’s early writings, particularly in his reflections on **human nature** and **alienation**. Marx's early engagement with German Idealism, especially through figures like Hegel and Feuerbach, brought him into indirect contact with Schelling’s ideas.
- **Key Connections**: Marx’s concept of **alienation** and his critique of mechanistic views of humanity may have been shaped by Schelling’s idea that nature and human beings are **living, dynamic processes**, not reducible to mere materialism.
### 4. **Martin Heidegger**
- **Influence**: Heidegger’s relationship with Schelling is explicit, especially in his 1936 lecture series on Schelling’s *Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom*. Schelling’s metaphysical ideas about the **ground of Being**, the **unconscious**, and the **tension between freedom and necessity** were foundational for Heidegger’s exploration of **Being** (*Sein*) and his concept of **existential freedom**.
- **Key Connections**: Heidegger’s notions of **Being as becoming**, **freedom**, and **concealment and unconcealment** in the process of Being can be traced back to Schelling’s ideas about the dynamic, processual nature of existence. Schelling’s emphasis on **nature** and its metaphysical depth also prefigures Heidegger’s critique of modern technology and **enframing**.
### 5. **Jean-Paul Sartre**
- **Influence**: Sartre’s existentialism, particularly his exploration of **freedom**, **nothingness**, and the **existential choice between good and evil**, shares key elements with Schelling’s philosophy. Though Sartre’s engagement with Schelling is not direct, the themes in Schelling’s work on the **irrational ground of Being** and the **tragic dimension of human freedom** anticipate some of Sartre’s ideas.
- **Key Connections**: Sartre’s notion of **radical freedom**, where human beings are condemned to be free and must define their essence through choices, echoes Schelling’s view that freedom is a fundamental aspect of human existence, tied to an indeterminate, chaotic ground.
### 6. **Carl Jung**
- **Influence**: Jung was directly influenced by Schelling’s ideas about the **unconscious**, particularly the view that the unconscious is not just a personal repository of repressed desires but a **cosmic, metaphysical force** that shapes both nature and the individual psyche. Schelling’s idea that both creativity and evil arise from the **unconscious ground of Being** played a significant role in the development of Jung’s concepts of the **collective unconscious** and the **shadow**.
- **Key Connections**: Schelling’s exploration of the **irrational**, the **unconscious**, and the **creative forces** at work in both nature and human beings parallels Jung’s theory that the **unconscious** contains both **destructive** and **creative** potentials. Jung’s concept of the **archetypes** and the **individuation process** reflects Schelling’s metaphysical views of human freedom and self-development.
### 7. **Jacques Lacan**
- **Influence**: Although Lacan was primarily influenced by Freud, he was also indirectly influenced by Schelling, especially through German Idealism and its explorations of the **unconscious**. Schelling’s view of the **unconscious as both a creative and destructive force** prefigures some of Lacan’s ideas about **desire, lack**, and the **unconscious as structured by language**.
- **Key Connections**: Lacan’s idea that **desire** is grounded in **lack** and that the unconscious is driven by forces that are not fully rational echoes Schelling’s ideas about the unconscious ground of Being, which is both creative and irrational.
### 8. **Maurice Merleau-Ponty**
- **Influence**: Merleau-Ponty was influenced by Schelling’s **philosophy of nature** and his idea that **Being** is dynamic and processual. Schelling’s notion of **nature as a living, self-organizing process** is reflected in Merleau-Ponty’s emphasis on the **primacy of perception** and the **interconnectedness of the body and the world**. Merleau-Ponty’s **phenomenology** of nature draws on Schelling’s view that nature is not a static object but a **living force** with its own internal principles.
- **Key Connections**: Merleau-Ponty’s idea of the **intertwining of subject and object** and his critique of Cartesian dualism echo Schelling’s rejection of a strict division between nature and spirit. Both thinkers emphasize the **creative forces** at work in the **natural world**.
### 9. **Slavoj Žižek**
- **Influence**: Žižek has extensively engaged with German Idealism, particularly Hegel and Schelling. He draws on Schelling’s **philosophy of freedom** and his exploration of the **irrational ground of existence**. Žižek’s notion of the **“parallax gap”**, where contradictions cannot be resolved into a higher unity, resonates with Schelling’s idea that the Absolute contains **irreducible tensions**.
- **Key Connections**: Žižek’s work on **ideology** and the **unconscious** draws on Schelling’s view of the **unconscious as a force of both creation and destruction**. Žižek also engages with Schelling’s critique of rational systems, which parallels Žižek’s critique of totalizing ideologies.
### 10. **The Frankfurt School (Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer)**
- **Influence**: Members of the **Frankfurt School**, especially Theodor Adorno, were influenced by Schelling’s critique of **Hegelian totality** and his emphasis on the **non-identity** of Being. Adorno’s concept of **negative dialectics**, which resists the subsumption of contradictions into a rational unity, reflects Schelling’s skepticism toward Hegelian rationalism and his focus on the **dynamic, unresolved nature** of reality.
- **Key Connections**: Adorno’s critique of **instrumental reason** and his emphasis on the **dialectic of Enlightenment**—where reason becomes complicit in domination—echo Schelling’s concern with the limitations of reason and his belief in the importance of **non-rational forces** in the development of freedom.
### 11. **Gilles Deleuze**
- **Influence**: Although Deleuze did not explicitly engage with Schelling, his philosophy shares important resonances with Schelling’s ideas about **nature, becoming**, and the **creative power of the unconscious**. Both thinkers reject static conceptions of Being and emphasize the **processual, dynamic nature of reality**. Deleuze’s notion of **immanence** and his focus on **creative forces** in nature and life echo Schelling’s ideas.
- **Key Connections**: Deleuze’s philosophy of **difference**, **multiplicity**, and the rejection of a unified totality resonates with Schelling’s rejection of **systematic closure** and his emphasis on the **irreducibility of tensions** in the Absolute.
### Conclusion
Schelling’s influence extends across a wide range of philosophical traditions, including **existentialism**, **phenomenology**, **psy
很有趣,他又睡著了,所以我再問一次,
Throughout the past two centuries, several philosophers have studied Schelling seriously and were influenced by his ideas. Here are some of the key figures:
### 1. **Friedrich Nietzsche**
- **Influence**: Schelling’s views on the **unconscious**, the **dynamic forces of nature**, and the role of **irrationality** influenced Nietzsche’s critiques of traditional metaphysics and rationalism. Nietzsche's ideas about the **will to power** and **Dionysian chaos** resonate with Schelling’s notions of the irrational ground of existence.
### 2. **Søren Kierkegaard**
- **Influence**: Kierkegaard was influenced by Schelling’s existential approach to **freedom**, especially the choice between **good and evil**. Kierkegaard’s concepts of the **leap of faith** and individual responsibility align with Schelling’s views on existential freedom.
### 3. **Karl Marx**
- **Influence**: Though indirect, Schelling’s dynamic view of **nature** and his rejection of mechanistic materialism influenced early Marxist ideas, particularly around **alienation** and the **living process** of human existence.
### 4. **Martin Heidegger**
- **Influence**: Heidegger studied Schelling deeply, especially in his 1936 lecture on Schelling’s *Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom*. Schelling’s ideas about the **ground of Being** and **freedom** shaped Heidegger’s own exploration of **Being**, **freedom**, and the **unconscious**.
### 5. **Jean-Paul Sartre**
- **Influence**: Schelling’s ideas about **radical freedom** and the tension between **good and evil** influenced existentialist themes in Sartre’s work, particularly his concept of **radical freedom** and the individual's struggle to define themselves.
### 6. **Carl Jung**
- **Influence**: Schelling’s metaphysical ideas about the **unconscious** as both **creative and destructive** informed Jung’s work on the **collective unconscious** and the **shadow**, which explores the darker, repressed aspects of the psyche.
### 7. **Jacques Lacan**
- **Influence**: Lacan’s work on the **unconscious** and **desire** has roots in Schelling’s notion of the **unconscious ground** of Being, where creative and destructive forces coexist. Lacan’s emphasis on the irrational aspects of human psychology aligns with Schelling’s focus on the unconscious.
### 8. **Maurice Merleau-Ponty**
- **Influence**: Schelling’s **philosophy of nature** influenced Merleau-Ponty’s views on **embodiment** and the **interconnectedness** of the human body and the natural world. Both emphasized the **dynamic** and **living** aspects of nature.
### 9. **Slavoj Žižek**
- **Influence**: Žižek has engaged with Schelling’s ideas about **freedom**, the **unconscious**, and the **paradoxical nature of Being**. Žižek’s concept of the **parallax gap** reflects Schelling’s emphasis on irreducible tensions in reality.
### 10. **Theodor Adorno**
- **Influence**: Adorno was influenced by Schelling’s critique of Hegelian rationalism and totality. Adorno’s **negative dialectics** and his critique of **instrumental reason** are informed by Schelling’s skepticism about the limits of rationality and the importance of non-rational forces.
### 11. **Gilles Deleuze**
- **Influence**: While Deleuze did not directly engage with Schelling, their ideas converge around the **dynamic**, **processual nature of Being**, and the rejection of static systems. Schelling’s notion of the **creative unconscious** parallels Deleuze’s focus on **immanence** and **creative forces**.
Schelling’s ideas have been foundational across a wide range of philosophical traditions, from **existentialism** to **phenomenology**, **psychoanalysis**, and **postmodernism**, influencing both **metaphysical** and **existential** explorations of freedom, nature, and the unconscious.
怎麼破解區塊鏈,聽說周二颱風,
柯文哲和新光金控,有什麼見不得人的關係,柯文哲和沈慶京的關係後面,依稀有共匪的影子 (shadow),
機體就是生命,你要理解,分子(尤其蛋白質和核酸)的立體存在,無以名狀,德勒茲的 fold,和拉岡的拓撲學,就是描述這個,無以名狀,
是否訂 TCPR,Total Access Subscription,
「當世界遽變,哲學就被喚醒」,
https://www.ebay.com/itm/185850486675,https://hughsongallery.com/viewWork?work=199,
精神分析則是,那個有名的,賴床裝睡,最後一個醒的,
Now,有趣的是,早醒的,手忙腳亂,一窩蜂隨波逐流,通常做不了什麼,
晚醒的,面對滿目瘡痍的廢墟,也做不了什麼,只能自稱當代史學家,
有沒有可能不醒,遂在夢中,過完千年,比如說,「秦始皇時睡去,醒來見到,包子扮演秦始皇」,從頭到尾拒絕醒來,就是中國歷史學家的定義,意思是說,大笑三聲,吞顆史蒂諾斯,他又匆匆睡去,意思是說,夢是唯一的現實,寧可夢到惡夢,不願醒來,親眼目睹惡夢,
對于西方人而言,只要反抗上帝,你就算存有哲學家,對于中國人而言,只要反抗共匪,你就算存有哲學家,你要理解,謝林說過,自由的定義,就是反抗 (resistance),
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814)
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831)
Johann Christian Friedrich Hölderlin (1770-1843)
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854)
German idealism is a philosophical movementthat emerged in Germany in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the 1780s and 1790s,[1] and was closely linked both with Romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment. The period of German idealism after Kant is also known as post-Kantian idealism or simply post-Kantianism.[2] One scheme divides German idealists into transcendental idealists, associated with Kant and Fichte, and absolute idealists, associated with Schelling and Hegel.[3]
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/German_idealism
The concept of **freedom** is a central concern for both Hegel and Schelling, but their interpretations of it are fundamentally different. These differences reflect their broader philosophical divergences, particularly in how they conceive the relationship between freedom, necessity, and the structure of Being. Here’s a detailed comparison of their views on freedom:
### 1. **Freedom and Rationality**
- **Hegel**: For Hegel, **freedom** is deeply connected to **rationality**. He argues that true freedom is not merely the ability to act arbitrarily but is realized when individuals act in accordance with the **rational order** of the world. In his dialectical philosophy, freedom is achieved through the recognition of **necessity**—by understanding and aligning with the rational, historical processes that guide the development of Spirit (Geist). According to Hegel, individuals become free when they grasp that their actions are part of a larger rational structure, where their subjective wills harmonize with the universal will of the ethical state or community. Freedom, in this sense, is the **self-realization of reason** in both individuals and society.
- **Schelling**: Schelling, in contrast, develops a more **existential and metaphysical** concept of freedom. For him, freedom is not primarily about rational self-realization but about the **ability to choose between good and evil**. He emphasizes the **irrational and unconscious** aspects of freedom, suggesting that freedom arises from the dark, chaotic ground of Being itself. In Schelling’s view, freedom is rooted in the tension between **necessity and contingency**, between the forces of light and darkness within the individual. His notion of freedom is less about aligning with rational necessity and more about confronting the **indeterminacy** and **radical choice** inherent in human existence.
### 2. **Freedom and Necessity**
- **Hegel**: In Hegel’s philosophy, freedom and necessity are reconciled through the dialectical process. He argues that **freedom is realized through necessity**—not in opposition to it. For Hegel, necessity is not a constraint on freedom but its condition. When individuals recognize the rational structures that govern reality, they understand that true freedom lies in acting according to these rational principles. Thus, freedom is not arbitrary but is the recognition of and participation in the rational development of Spirit. This means that **freedom and necessity** are two sides of the same coin in Hegel’s system: freedom is found in understanding and affirming the rational necessity of the world.
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s view of freedom is more **tragic** and **dualistic**. He sees freedom as existing in tension with necessity, rather than being fully reconciled with it. For Schelling, freedom requires a **ground of necessity** (what he calls the "dark ground" of Being), but this ground is **irrational** and cannot be fully understood or integrated into a rational system. In his **Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom** (1809), Schelling argues that true freedom involves the possibility of **evil** and **chaos**. Without the potential for evil, freedom would be meaningless. Therefore, unlike Hegel’s notion that freedom is realized through rational necessity, Schelling emphasizes that freedom involves a fundamental **indeterminacy** and the risk of moral failure. This makes freedom a more perilous, unpredictable, and open-ended concept in Schelling’s philosophy.
### 3. **Freedom and the Self**
- **Hegel**: In Hegel’s system, the **self** achieves freedom through **self-consciousness** and integration into the rational structures of society and history. Freedom is a process of **self-realization**, where individuals come to understand their role in the unfolding of the **universal** (Spirit). This process involves the individual recognizing that their **subjective will** is part of the broader objective rational order. In this way, Hegel’s concept of freedom is deeply tied to the individual’s participation in the **ethical life** of the community, where personal freedom is realized in alignment with the universal will of the state or society.
- **Schelling**: Schelling, however, focuses more on the **ontological and existential** aspects of freedom, particularly the **self’s confrontation with the unconscious**. He views freedom as the self’s struggle with the **irrational forces** within, which emerge from the unconscious ground of Being. In Schelling’s view, freedom is not simply self-realization in a rational sense but involves a constant **struggle** between light and darkness, between good and evil. The self is not fully integrated into a rational order but is caught in a **conflict** between these opposing forces. This gives Schelling’s notion of freedom a more **tragic and existential** dimension, where individuals must confront their own potential for evil and the irrational forces that shape their existence.
### 4. **Freedom and the Absolute**
- **Hegel**: Hegel’s conception of **freedom** culminates in the realization of the **Absolute**—the final, rational unity in which all contradictions are reconciled. For Hegel, freedom is not just individual autonomy but the **self-realization of Spirit** in which individuals understand that they are part of the universal, rational process of reality. Freedom is achieved when the individual recognizes their unity with the Absolute, and thus, with the rational necessity that governs all existence. In this sense, freedom for Hegel is ultimately **freedom through knowledge**—the knowledge that one’s actions are part of a larger, rational whole.
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s **Absolute**, on the other hand, is far more **mysterious and indeterminate**. For Schelling, the Absolute is not fully rational or knowable. Instead, it includes both rational and irrational elements, light and darkness, creation and destruction. As such, freedom, for Schelling, cannot be fully reconciled with the Absolute in the same way Hegel proposes. Rather, freedom always involves a **tension** with the unknown, with the unconscious ground of Being that resists total comprehension. The Absolute in Schelling’s philosophy is not a harmonious unity but a **dynamic, conflicting reality** in which freedom remains open-ended and unresolved.
### 5. **Moral and Existential Freedom**
- **Hegel**: In Hegel’s ethical philosophy, freedom is tied to the **ethical life** (*Sittlichkeit*), which is realized in the context of **society and the state**. For Hegel, the state represents the highest form of ethical life, where individual freedom and the universal will of the community are harmonized. Freedom is achieved when individuals act in accordance with the ethical norms and institutions that embody the rational will of Spirit. Therefore, Hegel’s concept of freedom is both **social and moral**, achieved through participation in the ethical order of society.
- **Schelling**: Schelling, by contrast, sees freedom as a more **personal and existential** matter. For Schelling, freedom is not simply about aligning with the rational structures of society or the state but involves a deeper confrontation with the **irrational** and **unconscious** forces within the self. Schelling’s idea of freedom is more about the individual’s ability to choose between good and evil, and to navigate the **existential tensions** that arise from this choice. His concept of freedom emphasizes the **tragic and paradoxical** nature of human existence, where individuals are always faced with the potential for both creation and destruction, good and evil.
### Summary of Key Differences
| **Aspect** | **Hegel** | **Schelling** |
|---------------------------|-------------------------------------------------|--------------------------------------------------|
| **Freedom and Rationality** | Freedom is rational self-realization, acting in harmony with necessity. | Freedom involves the irrational, rooted in the tension between good and evil. |
| **Freedom and Necessity** | Freedom is realized through recognizing necessity. | Freedom is in tension with necessity; it involves indeterminacy and risk. |
| **Self and Freedom** | The self becomes free by aligning with the rational order of Spirit and society. | The self experiences freedom through existential struggle with unconscious forces. |
| **Freedom and the Absolute**| Freedom culminates in the realization of the Absolute, a rational unity. | Freedom involves ongoing tension with the irrational aspects of the Absolute. |
| **Moral and Social Freedom**| Freedom is achieved in the ethical life, through participation in the state and society. | Freedom is personal and existential, involving the confrontation with good, evil, and the unconscious. |
### Conclusion
In summary, Hegel’s concept of freedom is more **rational, social, and systematic**, where freedom is realized through the alignment of the individual will with the **rational structures** of the world, culminating in the **Absolute**. Schelling’s concept of freedom is more **existential, metaphysical, and tragic**, emphasizing the tension between **rational and irrational** forces, and the individual’s struggle with the **unconscious** and the possibility of **evil**.
Hegel and Schelling, while both figures of **German Idealism**, developed significantly different philosophies, particularly after their early collaboration. Their divergence is most evident in how they conceive of **Being**, **freedom**, **nature**, and the **role of reason** in philosophy. While both were responding to the legacy of Kant and trying to address problems left by his critical philosophy, their approaches led them in quite different directions. Below are some of the key differences between the philosophies of Hegel and Schelling:
### 1. **System and Methodology: Dialectics vs. Dynamic Becoming**
- **Hegel’s System and Dialectic**: Hegel is best known for his **dialectical method**, which posits that reality unfolds through a process of **thesis, antithesis, and synthesis**. In this view, contradictions are not only resolved but integrated into a higher unity. For Hegel, the world, history, and thought evolve through this process, leading toward the realization of **absolute knowledge**—the point at which all contradictions are subsumed in the unity of the **Absolute**. His philosophy presents a **systematic, totalizing structure** in which everything finds its place in the rational development of Spirit (Geist), culminating in self-consciousness and freedom.
- **Schelling’s Dynamic and Processual View of Being**: Schelling, particularly in his later work, rejects such a totalizing system. He argues that reality is not a fully rational, self-contained process. Instead, he views Being as dynamic and fundamentally **irrational at its core**, composed of a tension between contradictory forces (light and darkness, freedom and necessity). Schelling’s metaphysical focus on **becoming** and the **unfolding of Being** is more open-ended and less systematic than Hegel’s dialectic. He sees existence as constantly evolving through conflict and contradiction, but without necessarily resolving those contradictions into a final unity as Hegel does.
### 2. **Nature**
- **Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature**: For Hegel, **nature** is part of the dialectical process but occupies a lower position in the hierarchy of the unfolding of Spirit. He views nature as the **externalization of the Idea**—a stage that Spirit must pass through on its way to self-consciousness. Nature is thus a necessary but incomplete and imperfect reflection of reason, a stepping stone toward higher forms of rationality found in human history, culture, and philosophy.
- **Schelling’s Philosophy of Nature**: In contrast, Schelling gives nature a much more **prominent and active role**. In his early **Naturphilosophie**, Schelling argues that nature is not merely a stage in the development of Spirit but a **self-organizing, living process** that exhibits freedom and creativity. For Schelling, nature is alive, dynamic, and imbued with spirit; it is not merely an object of thought but an active subject in its own right. Schelling’s view of nature as an unconscious striving toward self-expression anticipates later ecological and existential views of nature as inherently valuable and creative, not just a backdrop for human development.
### 3. **Freedom and Necessity**
- **Hegel’s Rational Freedom**: Hegel’s concept of **freedom** is bound up with the dialectical process. For Hegel, true freedom comes through the recognition of necessity—through understanding and internalizing the rational structures of reality. Freedom is achieved when individuals recognize themselves as part of the rational unfolding of Spirit, where their wills align with the ethical order of the state, history, and the universal. Thus, freedom is the **self-realization of reason** and the individual’s role in the rational whole.
- **Schelling’s Existential Freedom**: Schelling, on the other hand, emphasizes a more **existential and metaphysical conception of freedom**. For Schelling, freedom is not reducible to rational self-realization but involves a tension between **consciousness and the unconscious**, between **light and darkness**. Freedom for Schelling means the ability to choose between good and evil, and this capacity comes from the irrational depths of human existence. Schelling sees freedom as grounded in the **unconscious ground of Being**, where irrational forces like chaos and evil are as essential as rationality. In this way, Schelling’s concept of freedom is more radical and existential, focusing on the **tragic dimensions of human freedom** rather than its harmonious integration into a rational system.
### 4. **The Role of the Absolute**
- **Hegel’s Absolute**: Hegel’s **Absolute** is the ultimate reality, the totality in which all contradictions are resolved. For Hegel, the Absolute represents the culmination of the dialectical process, the point at which Spirit fully recognizes itself and achieves complete self-consciousness. The Absolute is the realization that all particular moments (thesis and antithesis) are reconciled in a higher unity (synthesis). Everything that exists, from nature to human history to thought, is a manifestation of the Absolute, which is ultimately **rational** and knowable through philosophy.
- **Schelling’s Absolute as Beyond Rationality**: Schelling’s **Absolute** differs from Hegel’s in that he views it as something that cannot be fully rationalized or known through reason alone. For Schelling, the Absolute is a **ground of Being** that contains both **irrational and rational elements**. It is not something that can be fully grasped by human consciousness or dialectical reasoning because it includes both light and darkness, order and chaos. The Absolute for Schelling is more mysterious, and any attempt to reduce it to a rational, self-conscious unity (as Hegel does) ignores its inherent indeterminacy and potential for contradiction.
### 5. **The Problem of Evil**
- **Hegel’s Resolution of Evil**: In Hegel’s dialectic, **evil** is a necessary stage in the process of development, something that is overcome and integrated into the final synthesis. For Hegel, evil is ultimately a **moment of alienation** that Spirit must pass through to achieve self-realization. It is part of the historical process and, in the end, is subsumed into the rational order of things. Evil, in this sense, is not a permanent or insurmountable force but something that reason ultimately reconciles.
- **Schelling’s Radical Understanding of Evil**: Schelling, however, takes a much more radical approach to **evil**. He argues that evil is not simply an absence of good or a stage in a rational process; rather, it is an **active, fundamental force** in the world that stems from the irrational ground of existence. In his **Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom**, Schelling suggests that evil is tied to the very structure of freedom—without the possibility of evil, there could be no true freedom. Evil, for Schelling, is an expression of the dark, unconscious forces that exist within the ground of Being itself. This makes evil a permanent possibility in human existence, not something that can be rationally resolved or explained away as part of a dialectical process.
### 6. **Philosophy of History**
- **Hegel’s Philosophy of History**: Hegel views history as the **rational development of Spirit** toward freedom and self-consciousness. History follows a teleological path, where each stage of human society represents a further realization of freedom. For Hegel, history has a **purpose**: the ultimate achievement of rational freedom and the reconciliation of individual wills with the universal will of the state. Historical events, wars, revolutions, and political movements are all part of the unfolding of Spirit toward its full realization in the modern world.
- **Schelling’s View of History**: Schelling, particularly in his later work, is far more skeptical of the idea that history follows a **rational or teleological path**. For Schelling, history is not the necessary unfolding of Spirit toward freedom but is more contingent, driven by both rational and irrational forces. Schelling views history as an **expression of the underlying tensions in Being**, including the conflict between freedom and necessity, light and darkness. There is no guarantee that history will culminate in rational freedom, and for Schelling, historical events are just as likely to be expressions of **unconscious drives** and **irrational forces** as they are of reason or Spirit.
### 7. **Aesthetic and Art**
- **Hegel’s View on Art**: For Hegel, art is a means by which **Spirit** expresses itself, but it ultimately ranks lower than **philosophy** and **religion** in terms of revealing truth. In his aesthetic philosophy, Hegel sees art as an important but preliminary stage in the development of Spirit’s self-consciousness. Art gives intuitive form to ideas, but it cannot fully express the rational truths that philosophy can articulate. As such, art’s role is **transitory** in the dialectical progression toward absolute knowledge.
- **Schelling’s Philosophy of Art**: In contrast, Schelling grants art a much more **central and elevated role**. For Schelling, art is the highest expression of **freedom** and **the Absolute** because it captures the tension between **consciousness and the unconscious**, between the finite and the infinite. Art, in Schelling’s view, transcends rational discourse and can express truths that philosophy cannot. It represents the **creative power of nature and spirit** and is a **revelation of the Absolute** in a way that cannot be fully explained by reason. For Schelling, art is not just a stepping stone in the dialectical process but the ultimate mode of expressing the dynamic and free nature of reality.
### Conclusion
In summary, the primary differences
ChatGPT 結論說到一半,就睡著了,所以我再問他一次,
The differences between the philosophies of **Hegel** and **Schelling** are significant, despite their early collaboration as prominent figures of **German Idealism**. These differences are most evident in their views on the nature of **Being**, **freedom**, **nature**, and the role of **reason** and **system** in philosophy. Here’s a breakdown of the key distinctions between their philosophies:
### 1. **Systematic Philosophy: Hegel’s Dialectic vs. Schelling’s Dynamic View**
- **Hegel**: Hegel’s philosophy is highly systematic. He is known for his **dialectical method**, where reality progresses through a process of **thesis, antithesis, and synthesis**. This method allows for the resolution of contradictions into a higher unity, leading to the ultimate realization of the **Absolute**, in which all contradictions are subsumed. Hegel’s system is comprehensive and aims to explain all aspects of reality, including nature, history, and spirit, through a rational, unfolding process.
- **Schelling**: Schelling, in contrast, moved away from a systematic approach. He critiqued Hegel’s dialectic for being too rational and totalizing. Instead, Schelling saw **Being** as a **dynamic and processual** force, where tension and contradiction are essential and irreducible. Schelling did not believe that reality could be fully captured by rational synthesis or resolved into a final unity. His view of Being emphasizes **becoming** rather than Hegel’s emphasis on the rational resolution of opposites.
### 2. **Conception of Nature**
- **Hegel**: For Hegel, **nature** is part of the dialectical development of **Spirit**. It represents an alienation of Spirit from itself, where Spirit becomes externalized and material. Nature, in Hegel’s system, is a lower stage in the development of Spirit and is characterized by its necessity and determinism. Nature is a stepping stone toward higher forms of rationality, particularly in human history and thought.
- **Schelling**: Schelling places much more emphasis on **nature as a living, self-organizing process**. In his **philosophy of nature** (*Naturphilosophie*), Schelling argues that nature itself is alive, dynamic, and expressive of spirit. For Schelling, nature is not merely an externalized stage of Spirit but a vital force that is essential to the unfolding of freedom. Nature is imbued with an unconscious striving that parallels human creativity and freedom. This contrasts sharply with Hegel’s more deterministic and rational conception of nature.
### 3. **Freedom and Necessity**
- **Hegel**: Hegel’s concept of **freedom** is closely tied to the dialectical process and is achieved through the recognition of **necessity**. In Hegel’s view, true freedom is not arbitrary but comes from aligning oneself with the rational order of the world. As individuals recognize their role in the larger unfolding of Spirit, they achieve freedom by realizing their place within this rational system. Freedom for Hegel is thus deeply linked to self-consciousness and the rational structure of reality.
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s notion of **freedom** is more existential and metaphysical. He sees freedom as rooted in the **tension between light and darkness**, between rationality and the **irrational ground** of Being. Schelling argues that freedom is not simply a matter of rational self-realization, as Hegel suggests, but involves a struggle between **consciousness and the unconscious**, between good and evil. Schelling’s concept of freedom emphasizes the **indeterminacy** and **radical choice** inherent in human existence, which is not fully explainable by rational necessity.
### 4. **The Absolute**
- **Hegel**: For Hegel, the **Absolute** is the final, all-encompassing reality in which all contradictions are resolved. It represents the culmination of the dialectical process and the full realization of Spirit’s self-consciousness. The Absolute is the ultimate synthesis where individual moments of reality are integrated into a coherent whole, and all differences are overcome through rational understanding. The Absolute, for Hegel, is knowable through philosophy.
- **Schelling**: Schelling’s view of the **Absolute** is different. He argues that the Absolute cannot be fully rationalized or understood through thought alone. For Schelling, the Absolute contains within it both **rational and irrational elements**, and it cannot be reduced to a final synthesis. The Absolute is a **ground of Being** that includes the possibility of **darkness, chaos, and evil**, which cannot be subsumed by rationality. Schelling believes that there is always something **mysterious** about the Absolute that resists total comprehension.
### 5. **The Problem of Evil**
- **Hegel**: In Hegel’s dialectical system, **evil** is ultimately a moment of alienation that can be reconciled through the rational development of Spirit. Evil is part of the historical and dialectical process and is ultimately integrated into a higher unity. For Hegel, evil is not a fundamental, irreconcilable force but rather a stage that Spirit must pass through on its way to self-consciousness and freedom.
- **Schelling**: Schelling takes a more radical approach to **evil**, viewing it as an **active, necessary force** that arises from the **unconscious ground of Being**. He argues that evil is a consequence of the **freedom** inherent in existence, and without the possibility of evil, there could be no true freedom. For Schelling, evil is not merely a temporary stage in a rational process but a **permanent possibility** that stems from the dark, irrational aspect of the Absolute. This makes Schelling’s treatment of evil much more existential and metaphysical than Hegel’s.
### 6. **Philosophy of History**
- **Hegel**: Hegel’s **philosophy of history** is teleological, meaning that history is seen as the rational development of **Spirit** toward freedom and self-consciousness. History, for Hegel, follows a dialectical process where each stage of development leads to greater freedom and self-understanding. The ultimate goal of history is the realization of freedom in the modern state, where individual wills align with the universal will.
- **Schelling**: Schelling is more skeptical of the idea that history follows a **rational or teleological path**. He sees history as contingent, shaped by both rational and **irrational forces**, including the interplay between freedom and necessity, light and darkness. For Schelling, history is an expression of the underlying tensions in Being and is not guaranteed to culminate in a rational resolution. Historical events, for Schelling, are as likely to be driven by unconscious or irrational forces as they are by reason.
### 7. **Art and Aesthetics**
- **Hegel**: In Hegel’s aesthetic philosophy, **art** is a stage in the development of Spirit, but it ranks below **philosophy** and **religion** in its ability to express truth. Art provides an **intuitive** form of truth, but for Hegel, it is ultimately surpassed by the **conceptual clarity** of philosophy. Art’s role is transitory, representing an early stage of Spirit’s development.
- **Schelling**: Schelling grants **art** a much more elevated role in his philosophy. For Schelling, art is the highest expression of **freedom** and the **Absolute**, because it uniquely captures the tension between **consciousness and the unconscious**, between the finite and the infinite. Art, for Schelling, transcends the limits of reason and expresses truths that philosophy cannot fully articulate. In this sense, art is not just a stepping stone to philosophy, but a direct revelation of the **creative power of Being**.
### Conclusion
The key differences between Hegel and Schelling center on the nature of **Being**, **freedom**, and the role of **reason** and **system** in their philosophies:
- Hegel’s philosophy is highly systematic, rational, and focused on the dialectical process that leads to the resolution of contradictions in the Absolute.
- Schelling rejects a purely rational system, emphasizing the dynamic, irrational, and processual aspects of Being. He highlights the **mysterious**, **unconscious**, and **irrational** dimensions of existence, giving more prominence to nature, freedom, and evil as fundamental and irreducible forces.
In short, Hegel’s philosophy is about the **rational reconciliation** of opposites, while Schelling’s is about the **creative and unresolved tension** between opposites, reflecting a more **existential** and **metaphysical** approach.